Now we get to Asger's proof.
Definition: If A is an almost disjoint family and B_0,B_1\subseteq A, then B_0, B_1 have uniformly bounded intersection by k if for any x\in B_0, y\in B_1, x\cap y\subseteq k.
Definition: A polarization of A is a countable partition \{F_n\}_{n\in\omega} of \{(x,y)\in A^2:x\neq y\} such that for each n, \mathrm{proj}_0 F_n and \mathrm{proj}_1 F_n have uniformly bounded intersection by some k.
Here \mathrm{proj}_0 and \mathrm{proj}_1 are the projections to the left and right coordinates, respectively.
The polarization will help us get to a countable situation where we can diagonalize. We will show the following lemmas:
Lemma 1: \mathbf{\Sigma}^1_1 almost disjoint families have polarizations.
Lemma 2: If an almost disjoint family has a polarization, then it is not maximal.
This would prove Mathias's result again.
To prove Theorem 2, we can use Lemma 2 plus the following (which we won't prove here):
Lemma 3: \mathrm{OCA}_\infty + every set of reals has the perfect set property implies that every almost disjoint family has a polarization. (\mathrm{OCA}_\infty is a strengthening of the open coloring axiom)
Lemma 4: \mathrm{OCA}_\infty holds in Solovay's model.
Proof of Lemma 1: Suppose T\subseteq [\omega]^{<\omega}\times [\omega]^{<\omega}\times [\omega]^{<\omega} is such that p[T]:=\{(x,y)\in ([\omega]^{\omega})^2: \exists t \, (t,x,y)\textrm{ is a branch of T}\} is equal to \{(x,y)\in A^2:x\neq y\} which exists since that set is analytic (this is a basic descriptive set theory representation of an analytic set).
Consider the set of nodes (\tau, r,s) such that every extension (\tau',r',s') has r'\cap s'=r\cap s. Given such (\tau,r,s), let F=p[T_{(\tau,r,s)}]. Then \mathrm{proj}_0 F and \mathrm{proj}_1 F have uniformly bounded intersection by \max(r\cap s).
We can perform a countable length derivative process, iteratively removing such nodes from T. This will terminate in countably many steps (since there are only countably many nodes) and the tree with no such nodes cannot have infinite branches, as this would contradict the almost disjointness of A.
Proof of Lemma 2: First we make the following observation: if A is an uncountable almost disjoint family and polarized by \{F_n\}_{n\in \omega}, then there is a sequence B_0,B_1,\ldots of uncountable subsets of A such that B_i has uniformly bounded intersection with \bigcup_{j>i} B_j and B_0=\mathrm{proj}_0 F_n for some n.
To prove the observation, take n such that \mathrm{proj}_0 F_n and \mathrm{proj}_1 F_n are both uncountable. Take B_0=\mathrm{proj}_0 F_n. Now \mathrm{proj}_1 F_n is polarized by \{F_m\cap (\mathrm{proj}_1 F_n)^2\}_{m\neq n}. So we can iterate this process for \omega steps, giving the observation.
Suppose B_i are as above. Set X_{B_i}=\bigcup B_i. Note that the X_{B_i} form an almost disjoint family, because of the uniform bound on the intersections of sets from B_i, B_j for any given i,j.
This process is the first step in an iterative procedure, A_0=A, B_{0,i}=B_i, X_{0,i}=X_i. The iteration will extend transfinitely. At stage \alpha, let A_\alpha be A minus the free ideal generated by all of the X_{\beta,i}, \beta<\alpha. Define B_{\alpha,i} and X_{\alpha,i} in the same way as above. This terminates after countably many steps, since each B_{\alpha_i} is a different \mathrm{proj}_0 F_n. Let \lambda be the length of this procedure: the termination condition is that A_\lambda is countable. Now we can use the usual diagonalization to find a set almost disjoint from A_\lambda and each of the X_{\alpha_i}. This set will be almost disjoint from every member of A, so A cannot be maximal.
No comments:
Post a Comment