Duality Theorem: Suppose I is a precipitous ideal on Z and \mathbb{P} is any partial order. If: there is a further generic extension of the extension by P(Z)/I so that if j:V\rightarrow M\subseteq M\subseteq V[G] is the ultrapower embedding from G\subseteq P(Z)/I, there is H\subseteq \mathbb{P} generic over V and \hat{H}\subseteq j(\mathbb{P}) generic over M and some extension of j to \hat{j}:V[H]\rightarrow M[\hat{H}].
Then: there is a \mathbb{P}-name for an ideal J on Z and a P(Z)/I-name for an ideal K on j(\mathbb{P}) and a canonical isomorphism \iota:\mathcal{B}(\dot{\mathbb{P}\ast P(Z)/J})\equiv \mathcal{B}(P(Z)/I\ast j(\mathbb{P})/\dot{K}).
So a very general statement of lifting a generic ultrapower map to a forcing extension gives a useful isomorphism for computing P(Z)/J in the generic extension by \mathbb{P}. We remark that in some cases, this will be an equivalence.
Note: In what follows, we tacitly identify all of the posets involved with their Boolean completions. Occasionally for emphasis, this identification will be explicit.
Proof: Assume (1). There is some A\in I^+ and some P(Z)/I-name for a forcing \dot{\mathbb{Q}} so that
A\Vdash_{P(Z)/I}(\Vdash_\dot{\mathbb{Q}} \dot{H_0}\subseteq j(\mathbb{P}) \textrm{ is generic over }M \textrm{ and }H:=j^{-1}[H_0]\subseteq \mathbb{P}\textrm{ is generic over }V).
Note that the set \{p\in\mathbb{P}:\quad \Vdash_{P(A)/I\ast \mathbb{Q}} j(p)\not\in H_0\} cannot be dense, since it is the complement of the generic j^{-1}[H_0]. So there is p_0\in \mathbb{P} so that for all p\le p_0, \| j(p)\in H_0 \|_{P(A)/I\ast \mathbb{Q}}\neq 0. We will constrain ourselves to work below this p_0 in \mathbb{P} and below A in P(Z)/I. For simplicity, assume that A=Z and p_0=1_\mathbb{P}.
In V^{P(Z)/I}, define
K=\{p\in j(\mathbb{P}):\quad \Vdash_{\mathbb{\dot{Q}^G}} p\not\in H_0\}.
Let G\ast h be generic for P(Z)/I\ast j(\mathbb{P})/K. From the j(\mathbb{P})/K-generic h, we can define a j(\mathbb{P})-generic \hat{H}=\{p:[p]_K\in h\}.
Claim: The following properties of H_0 are also true of \hat{H}:
- \Vdash_{P(Z)/I\ast \mathbb{Q}} \hat{H} is j(\mathbb{P})-generic over M.
- \Vdash_{P(Z)/I\ast \mathbb{Q}} j^{-1}[\hat{H}] is \mathbb{P}-generic over V.
- For all p\in \mathbb{P}, \not\Vdash_{P(Z)/I\ast \mathbb{Q}} j(p)\not\in \hat{H}.
Proof of Claim: For (1), suppose D\in M is open dense in j(\mathbb{P}). Then \{[d]_K:d\in D\textrm{ and }d\not\in K\} is dense in j(\mathbb{P})/K. Otherwise, there would exist p\in j(\mathbb{P})/K so that p\wedge d\in K for all d\in D. But this is impossible because we could then force with \mathbb{Q} over V[G] to get a generic H_0 containing p (as p\not\in K), and then H_0\cap D=\emptyset, contradicting genericity of H_0 over M.
The remaining parts of the claim can be checked similarly, and are left as an exercise. \Box.
Now let e:\mathbb{P}\rightarrow \mathcal{B}(P(Z)/I\ast \dot{j(\mathbb{P})/K}) be defined by e(p)=\|j(p)\in \hat{H}\|.
By (3) of the claim above, \mathrm{ker}(e)=0. Also e preserves Boolean operations simply by the elementarity of j. By (2) of the claim, e is a regular embedding (maps maximal antichains pointwise to maximal antichains).
Exercise: e:\mathbb{P}\rightarrow \mathbb{Q} is a regular embedding iff for every q\in\mathbb{Q} there is p\in \mathbb{P} so that for every p'\le p, e(p') is compatible with q.
Thus, if H\subseteq \mathbb{P} is generic over V, we can force with the quotient \mathcal{B}(P(Z)/I\ast \dot{j(\mathbb{P})/K})/e"H over V[H] to obtain a generic G\ast h for P(Z)/I\ast j(\mathbb{P})/K. By the definition of e, we have j_G"H\subseteq \hat{H}, where \hat{H} is defined from h as before. So we can extend the embedding j_G to \hat{j}:V[H]\rightarrow M[\hat{H}].
In V[H] we can finally define J=\{A\subseteq Z:1\Vdash [\mathrm{id}]\not\in \hat{j}(A)\}, where the forcing is with the quotient \mathcal{B}(P(Z)/I\ast \dot{j(\mathbb{P})/K})/e"H. In V, let
\iota(p,\dot{A})=e(p)\wedge \|[id]\in\hat{j}(\dot{A})\|.
Exercise: \iota is order and incompatibility preserving.
It remains to show that the range of \iota is dense. So take an arbitrary (B,\dot{q})\in P(Z)/I\ast j(P)/K. By strengthening this condition, we may assume without loss of generality that there is f:Z\rightarrow \mathbb{P} in V so that B\Vdash [[f]_M]_K=\dot{q}.
By regularity of e (using the characterization in the exercise), there is a p so that for all p'\le p, e(p')\wedge (B,\dot{q})\neq 0. Let \dot{A} be a \mathbb{P}-name for a subset of Z such that p \Vdash \dot{A}=\{z\in B: f(z)\in H\} and \neg p \Vdash \dot{A}\in J^+.
We check that (p,\dot{A}) is actually a condition, which involves checking that p\Vdash \dot{A}\in J^+. So take a generic G\ast \dot{h} containing e(p)\wedge (B,\dot{q}) (which is nonzero by choice of p). Then clearly B\in G and since [[f]_M]_K=q\in h, we have [f]_M=j(f)([\mathrm{id}])\in\hat{H}. Therefore [\mathrm{id}]\in \hat{j}(A), so this generic G\ast \dot{h} shows that it is not forced by \mathcal{B}(P(Z)/I\ast \dot{j(\mathbb{P})/K}/e"H that [\mathrm{id}]\not\in \hat{j}(A)\}.
By definition \iota:=\iota(p,\dot{A}) forces j(p)\in \hat{H} and [\mathrm{id}]\in\hat{j}(\dot{A}). Since \hat{j} extends j and it's forced that \dot{A}\subseteq B, \iota must force B\in G. And since j(p)\Vdash_{j(\mathbb{P})} j(\dot{A})=j(\{z:j(f)(z)\in \hat{H}\}), \iota must force \dot{q}=[j(f)(\mathrm{id})]_K\in h. \Box
Remark: Suppose K as in the Duality Theorem is forced to be principal, i.e., there is m so that \Vdash K=\{p\in j(\mathbb{P}:p\le \neg m\}.
Then the Duality Theorem is easily seen to be an equivalence.
We can compute some nice properties of the ideal J arising from the previous theorem.
Proposition: Using the notation of the previous theorem, J is forced to be precipitous, with the same completeness as I. If I is normal, then J is also normal. Also, if \bar{G}\subseteq P(Z)/J is generic over V[H] and G\ast h=\iota[H\ast \bar{G}] and \hat{j}:V[H]\rightarrow M[\hat{H}] are as before, then V[H]^Z/{\bar{G}}=M[\hat{H}] and \hat{j} is the ultrapower embedding.
Finally, we relate J to the ideal in V[H] generated by I.
Proposition: Suppose K as in the Duality Theorem is forced to be principal, with m so that \Vdash K=\{p\in j(\mathbb{P}):p\le \neg m\}. Suppose further that there exist f and A so that A\Vdash \dot{m}=[f]_G and \dot{B} is a \mathbb{P}-name for \{z\in A: f(z)\in \dot{H}\}. Then \bar{I}\upharpoonright B=J\upharpoonright B, and A\setminus B\in J, where \bar{I} is the ideal in V[H] generated by I.
No comments:
Post a Comment